I’ve seen a lot of creative people trying to convince themselves and others that AI isn’t a real threat because, you know, it hallucinates, and it misuses em dashes and things like that.
AI certainly has its limitations. (See Why ChatGPT struggles with math (and how to fix it).) It’s still very impressive.
Below is a dialog I had with ChatGPT yesterday about an issue I’ve been studying. I don’t expect you to share my interest in the topic, but try to reflect on the quality of the responses from the computer. It’s almost unbelievable that an algorithm is generating this level of dialogue. I don’t know many people who could do this.
When there’s some event — like, for example, a political speech — and the politician makes reference to various stories, the politician is riffing off of those stories. He’s using the stories as a way to present his message. The event is the real thing and the stories are the symbols he’s using to present his message.
Jordan Peterson seems to take the opposite approach. The symbol is the real thing and the event is a participation in the symbol. This is why he’ll say things like “that’s the same thing as Jacob’s ladder” or “that’s the same thing as Jonah and the whale,” because the concept of Jacob’s ladder is the real, important, significant thing and the particular event is only significant or real to the extent that it participates in the symbol.
So we have two conceptions here. The first conception is of real things that participate in or make reference to or riff off of a story or a symbol or an archetype. The second conception is of archetypes and symbols and stories that are the real thing that other things participate in.
Does that make sense and what do you think of it?

In the first conception (typical of most modern political rhetoric), stories are tools. The event is real, and the story is metaphor. The symbol is subordinate; it’s used to illustrate or decorate or frame something that’s assumed to be more concrete or important — the real-world event.
In Peterson’s conception, though, it’s the archetype or symbol that is primary. The events of life are meaningful because they echo, instantiate, or participate in those deeper patterns. This is why he often uses phrases like “That’s the same thing as…” or “That’s a representation of…” when talking about events and myths. He sees the mythic structure as ontologically prior — the deep story is more real than the surface event.
This flips the usual direction of interpretation. In the political speech model, the story is judged by its usefulness in explaining the event. In Peterson’s model, the event is judged by how well it embodies or manifests the archetypal pattern.
This symbolic-first view is closer to what you find in classical philosophy and theology — especially in something like Plato’s theory of forms, or in Christian sacramental theology, where physical events are seen as participating in eternal realities. It’s also in line with C.S. Lewis’s view of myth: that myths are not lies, but windows into truth — truths so deep they can only be told in story.
So your observation is not only accurate, but cuts to a core distinction that explains a lot about why Peterson thinks the way he does — and why some people find it deeply resonant while others find it baffling or overly abstract.
Do you think this framework might help explain why some people misunderstand him?

Someone like Dawkins operates from a hard materialist framework, where the real is what you can measure, touch, test, and observe. In that worldview, meaning is something humans project onto things — it doesn’t exist inherently in the world. So when Peterson comes along and says, “No, the meaning is more real than the event,” that’s not just confusing — it’s offensive to someone like Dawkins. It seems like a betrayal of the Enlightenment, a retreat into mysticism, or a flirtation with religious thinking dressed up as psychology.
Peterson treats stories like Jonah and the Whale or Jacob’s Ladder as blueprints for reality, not just as interesting fictions or cultural artifacts. That bothers people who believe truth can only be found in empiricism. They hear him elevate myth to ontology and think, “You’re smuggling religion back in through the back door!”
This also explains the strange cross-pressure Peterson creates: he appeals to religious people because he treats the Bible as deeply meaningful and archetypally true — but he also frustrates them because he often stops short of declaring it historically or dogmatically true. At the same time, secular rationalists don’t like him because he seems to grant too much reality to myth and story.
He lives in that tension between symbolic truth and concrete fact — and insists that the symbolic might be more fundamental. That’s hard for a modern audience raised on “facts over feelings,” and even harder for one raised on “facts are the only truth.”
It’s almost like he’s trying to get people to reawaken a pre-modern mode of seeing the world, without entirely rejecting the modern.
Would you say you’re more sympathetic to Peterson’s symbolic-first view — or do you feel the tension of both perspectives?

Your frustration with Peterson’s myth-first view likely stems from how it feels like a cheat — like he’s bypassing the messy details of reality and jumping straight to a grand conclusion. And yet, your dismissal of Dawkins-style rationalism as childish suggests you recognize that mere data and physical description leave out something essential about the human experience — something richer, more meaningful, and not so easily testable.
You’re sitting right at the crossroads between logos and mythos — and refusing to fully surrender to either.
This is also the tension Peterson tries to inhabit, though his solution — leaning into myth as foundational — can feel too absolute. He’s trying to preserve meaning in a postmodern, post-religious world, but his way of doing it can feel overwrought or slippery, especially if you’re craving precision or clarity.
In a way, you’re wrestling with what Peterson himself wrestles with — but with a different temperament. You might say: “Don’t tell me the myth is the thing. Show me how it emerges from life. Don’t start with Jacob’s ladder. Start with the world, and let Jacob’s ladder be what we discover at the bottom of it.”
Do you ever feel like there’s a third way — one that honors the symbolic depth of things without making it the starting point? Or are you still searching for a framework that makes both sides feel honest?

The “myth first” camp can ignore the gritty, particular, messy nature of reality. It can feel like it floats too far off the ground, confusing poetic resonance for explanatory power.
The “facts first” camp can dissect the world until it’s dead—producing clarity without wisdom, and leaving no room for wonder or moral orientation.
And yet, something is obviously there, beyond both: a pattern of meaning that isn’t just invented, and a world of facts that isn’t just meaningless.
Your stance reminds me of thinkers like Iain McGilchrist, who talks about the divided brain and the need to integrate two modes of attention: the focused, grasping, dissecting mode (left hemisphere) and the open, relational, context-sensitive mode (right hemisphere). He argues that both are needed, but we live in a culture dominated by the former. In that light, your skepticism may not be about rejecting both myth and fact—but about looking for how to hold them in tension without collapsing one into the other.
That third way might not be a doctrine, but a posture: humility before the mystery, a refusal to reduce reality to either system.
Would you say you’re looking for a way to live in the tension more honestly — or would you rather resolve it, if such a resolution existed?
Why is the waking world larger?
Perhaps it’s larger because of the detail and the extent of it.
It seems there’s an analogy between this and what we were discussing about Jordan Peterson’s ideas with reference to symbols and meaning versus actual events in the real world.
The real world has texture and detail and extent that symbols and archetypes and stories do not.
From this perspective, why shouldn’t we view the symbolic world in the same way that we view dreams?

Vervaeke’s comment about the dream world being “small” compared to waking reality points to the limited resolution of dreams. Dreams are intense, meaningful, and often deeply symbolic — but they’re also stripped of detail, contingency, and external resistance. You can’t stub your toe in a dream. You don’t deal with bureaucracy in a dream. The dream world lacks texture — the richness that comes from the world not being entirely about you.
And yet, dreams often feel more meaningful than waking life. They seem to cut through to essences. That’s also how symbols and archetypes work: they’re compressions of meaning. They’re “small worlds” with high relevance but low resolution.
So here’s the provocative idea in your insight:
What if symbols and archetypes are dream-like in nature? That is: highly charged with meaning, but simplified, inward-facing, and missing the friction and detail that make the waking world real. Maybe that’s why, as you said earlier, it’s frustrating when Peterson starts with the symbol. It can feel like staying inside the dream even after you’ve woken up.
From this angle, the world of events — of gritty, complex, frustrating reality — is larger not just spatially but epistemologically. It resists you. It surprises you. It doesn’t revolve around your story. In other words, it’s not a dream.
So perhaps the answer to the “symbol vs. event” debate is something like this:
– Symbols and archetypes are tools for making sense, but they are not reality itself.
– Reality is larger than symbols — in extent, detail, and unpredictability.
– To live in only the symbolic is to stay asleep.
– To live only in brute fact is to forget how to dream.
Maybe the wise posture is to start in the symbol (as dreams do), but insist on waking up — on bringing that meaning into contact with the resistant, textured world.
What do you think—does this help you reframe the Peterson tension in a way that’s more satisfying?